basic constructions:
strong axioms
further
In classical mathematics, the ultrafilter theorem is a theorem about ultrafilters, proved as a standard application of Zorn's lemma. In the foundations of mathematics, however, it is interesting to consider which results are implied by it or equivalent to it (very few imply it without being equivalent, other than those that imply the full axiom of choice itself).
Given a set , every proper filter on may be extended to an ultrafilter (that is, a maximal proper filter) on .
Given a proper filter on , consider the poset of proper filters that refine (contain) , ordered by inclusion (reverse refinement). Of course, is in this poset. Given a chain of proper filters that refine , the union is a proper filter that refines and is an upper bound of . By Zorn's lemma, there is a proper filter maximal among those that refines , which is therefore maximal among all proper filters.
Although this proof uses Zorn’s lemma, the statement itself is weaker. In particular, it is weaker than the axiom of choice (even assuming the principle of excluded middle).
Although the ultrafilter theorem is weaker than the axiom of choice, it can be used to prove quite a few results that are traditionally proved using Zorn's lemma (or some other thing equivalent to the axiom of choice). For example, it can be used to prove
the Hahn–Banach theorem (which in turn implies existence of Lebesgue non-measurable sets),
the prime ideal theorem for rigs, rings, and Boolean algebras,
that every formally real field can be totally ordered,
existence and uniqueness of algebraic closures (see splitting field),
existence of non-trivial ultraproducts,
the compactness theorem and completeness theorem for first-order logic (see below)
as a partial list. An enlightening discussion of the things one might expect to be able to prove using the ultrafilter theorem is given here at MO.
However, in other respects, the ultrafilter theorem is very weak as a “choice principle”. For example, it is too weak to prove the axiom of countable choice (so for example, it cannot prove that a countable union of countable sets is countable), a fact exhibited in Cohen’s first model for the failure of the axiom of choice (where even countable choice fails but the ultrafilter theorem holds). It therefore cannot prove the axiom of dependent choice either.
It can prove some traditional applications of dependent choice. For example, it can be used to linearly order any set. From there it can be used to prove that a countable union of nonempty finite sets is countable, which in turn can be used to establish the weak König lemma; see here.
In constructive mathematics, the ultrafilter principle also implies De Morgan's law, which means that the poset of truth values is a De Morgan Heyting algebra. Any topos with an internal ultrafilter principle is thus a De Morgan topos.
Here are several statements equivalent (internal to an arbitrary topos) to the ultrafilter theorem.
The first three are, if you work through the definitions, almost direct rephrasings of the theorem above:
Every net has a universal subnet. (We must define ‘subnet’ and ‘universal net’ properly to make this work, at which point the equivalence is immediate.)
The Boolean prime ideal theorem: every proper ideal in a Boolean ring is contained in a prime ideal. (Stronger formulations of the Boolean prime ideal theorem also follow.)
The Stone representation theorem: every Boolean algebra is a subalgebra of some function algebra into the initial Boolean algebra. (Stronger formulations of the Stone representation theorem also follow.)
These basic results in logic are equivalent to the ultrafilter theorem:
Consistency: if a set of formulas in propositional classical logic is syntactically consistent (proves no contradiction), then it is semantically consistent (has a model). (The converse is immediate; stronger formulations of the consistency theorem, including for predicate logic, also follow.)
Compactness: if every finite subset of has a model, then so does . (The converse is immediate; stronger formulations of the compactness theorem, including for predicate logic, also follow.)
Various characterisations of compact spaces are equivalent to the ultrafilter theorem:
Given a set , the space (in the product topology) is compact. (This can be seen as a very weak form of the Tychonoff theorem below.)
More generally, if every ultrafilter on a convergence space is convergent, then is compact. (The converse is immediate.)
A uniform space is compact if it is complete and totally bounded (i.e. it is Bishop-compact). (The converse is immediate.)
These classical results in analysis are equivalent to the ultrafilter theorem in a Boolean topos with natural numbers object:
The Tychonoff theorem for Hausdorff spaces: any product of compact Hausdorff spaces is compact; equivalently, any product of compact Hausdorff spatial locales is spatial. (If we drop the Hausdorff condition, then the result is equivalent to the full axiom of choice.)
Stone–Čech compactification: the compact Hausdorff spaces form a reflective subcategory of Top. (The classical result that they form a reflective subcategory of the category of completely regular Hausdorff spaces is enough; the classical result that the reflection is a dense embedding on also follows.)
Banach–Alaoglu theorem: the closed unit ball of the double dual of a Banach space is weak* compact. (The result for separable spaces does not require the ultrafilter theorem.)
Of course, since the ultrafilter theorem is independent of ZF, there are models in which it fails. More strongly, however, there are apparently models of ZF in which every ultrafilter (on every set) is principal. See this MO answer.
Various equivalences with the ultrafilter theorem are stated and proved (in ZF) in
See a summary (in GIF!): page 1 and page 2.
It's possible that I've made some mistakes above in deciding which of these use excluded middle or the existence of a natural numbers object. (I very much doubt that any of them use replacement.)
For the ultrafilter principle in constructive mathematics:
Last revised on June 14, 2021 at 23:55:06. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.